Before I get into the mathemes themselves, I’d like
to lay out the four terms by which we will need to read each matheme.
In Lacan,
the “$” can be read as the barred or split subject. As Bruce Fink points out, "The castrated subject is the barred subject, the subject under the bar: it is a product of every attempt and intent to signify to the other" (73) Since my goal is to move
these mathemes into the realm of OOO, we will need to read the “$” as the split
object of onticology. As Levi Bryant states in The Democracy of Objects, “…[S]plit-objects refers not to a
physical split such as the idea that objects can always be broken in half or
divided, but rather to the split between the virtual proper being of objects or
their powers and their local manifestations or qualities” (70). There are a
couple of points that need to be made about this split, though. First, every
object (including humans) is split between a virtual proper being and local
manifestations. This means that “$” is representative of all objects, including
the split subject in Lacan. Second, this “$” is the object proper, meaning that
“$” represents precisely this onticological idea of an object consisting of
both a virtual proper being and local manifestations (whether experienced or
not by another object).
$ = Split ObjectS1 = Local ManifestationS2 = Environmenta = Withdrawal or Virtual Proper Being
Next, we will need to read Lacan’s “S1”
not as a master signifier, but as an object’s local manifestation. For Lacan, as Fink points out, “An S1 is often recognizable in analysis by
the fact that the analysand repeatedly butts up against the term; it may be a
term like ‘death,’ for instance, or any other term that seems opaque to the
analysand and that always seems to put an end to associations instead of
opening things up” (Fink 77). In other words, the master signifier is an actualization
of a lack in the subject, but an actualization that is so strong or frequently
repeated that it blocks further actualizations. Onticologically, however, the
local manifestation can be seen as a quality or actualization of a power in the
object’s virtual proper being, often when it comes into an external or
exo-relation with another object. As Bryant notes, “As a function of the
exo-relations objects enter into with other objects, the attractors defining
the virtual space of a substance can be activated in a variety of different
ways, actualizing objects in a variety of different ways at the level of local
manifestations” (Bryant 114). But like the master signifier that could keep the
analysand from opening up, in a sense defining him, there is also a danger to
each local manifestation. Because local manifestations are actualizations of withdrawn
virtual or potential powers in the object, each object runs the risk of
reducing the entire split object into only its local manifestations. “It is for
this reason,” Bryant argues, “that the confusion of objects with their actualization
in local manifestations always spells theoretical disaster, for in doing so we
foreclose the volcanic potentials harbored in the depths of objects”
(114). Therefore, like Lacan’s master
signifier, each local manifestation harbors the danger of eclipsing the
split-object by reducing it to its local manifestations at the detriment of its
virtual proper being.
We will also need to read Lacan’s S2 in
a modified way, since for Lacan the S2 represented at times
knowledge and “‘other’ signifiers” (75). Fink explains how for Lacan it was the
S2 or the group of signifiers, the chain of potential signifiers
that gave meaning to the master signifier. In other words, the S2 is
always multiple, S2s. And, “If S1 is not in place, every S2
is somehow unbound. The S2s have relations amongst themselves; they
may be strung together in perfectly ordinary ways by a psychotic [someone who
has no master signifier], but they do not seem to affect him or her in any sense;
they are somehow independent of him or her” (75). Therefore, the S2
is a chain or group of signifiers that retroactively brings about the meaning
of an S1. In onticological terms, however, we need to read this S2
as representing the environment of the object. For Bryant, though, “[T]he
environment is not a container of substances or systems that precedes the
existence of substances or systems. There is no environment ‘as such’ existing
out there in the world…Rather, we have as many environments as there are
substances in the universe, without it being possible to claim that all of
these systems are contained in a single environment” (146). Environments, or S2s,
are again plural. And because of the ongoing and metonymical form of
identification, environments can be seen as in-formational. As Bryant puts it, “While
there is indeed an identity to the object, in the sense that it has a virtual
endo-structure that persists across time, this identity is always manifesting
itself in a variety of ways” (166). In this sense, objects take on new forms
and actualize new local manifestations, so that “[i]n both allopoietic and
autopoitic systems, information is an event that makes a difference by
selecting a system-state” (166). In this way, the environment has an effect on
the object retroactively, by producing the space available for the object’s
local manifestations, so that the system or virtual proper being of the object
is what constitutes the environment. As Bryant points out, “Although this
distinction refers to two domains (system and environment), the distinction
itself originates from one of these domains: the system” (144). S2,
or the realm of other possible signifiers, can effectively be read as the
object’s environment, since both operate as multiple arenas by which the S1
becomes actualized retroactively.
Finally, for Lacan the object cause of desire is
represented by the small “a.” Fink describes object (a) as “the leftover of
that process of constituting an object, the scrap that evades the grasp of symbolization.
It is a remainder that there is something else, something perhaps lost, perhaps
yet to be found” (94). In short, object (a) is that which is in excess of every
relation between S1 and S2. It is, speaking onticologically, that
which withdraws from any relation. It is the object’s virtual proper being. As
Bryant argues, “objects are always in excess of any of their local
manifestations, harboring hidden volcanic powers irreducible to any of their
manifestations in the world” (70). So that “[w]ithin the framework of onticology,
the claim that objects are withdrawn from other objects is the claim that
1)substances are independent of or are not constituted by their relations to
other objects, and 2) that objects are not identical to any qualities they happen
to locally manifest” (70). Much like Lacan’s object (a) which escapes (and is
thus produced by) every signifying relation, the virtual proper being of an
object withdraws (and is inferred) from any of the object’s relations and local
manifestations.
http://lareviewofbooks.org/article.php?id=844
ReplyDelete-dmf
Hi Nathan, great blog! I'm a little confused on this: you haven't established why it might be useful to try to understand OOO by "translating" it from Lacanian concepts. And from what I read here, so appears to be lost in the translation (not least of which is the fundamental role of lack) that it leaves me wondering, 1) what is the use of this translation/comparison? and 2) does OOO really have any bearing on Lacan's topology of desire, considering OOO makes no mention of the subject, and appears (to my limited knowledge) to not distinguish between "objects" who use language (subjects who are incorporated into the chain of signification) and "objects" who do not.
ReplyDeleteI'm not totally dumb, but I struggle every time I attempt to get some basic sense of why OOO exists at all from texts written by its champions. Of course, to read Lacan is to struggle with esotericism as well, but speaking as someone coming from a much more pronounced Lacanian background, this post leaves me "lacking" as to a basic understanding of what OOO is supposed to be/do. I'll keep reading and trying, of course. But does Lacan's philosophy really have anything to do with OOO?
Hello eben,
DeleteThanks for reading. As to the Lacanian aspect of OOO, I find that Lacan helps me to better understand Levi Bryant's objects and his OOO in general. Perhaps this is because Levi, himself, was a practicing analyst or because his object is essentially split (much like Lacan's subject). But more than anything, I think what Lacan brings to the OOO table is a structural understanding of relations that deal with withdrawal -- or perhaps a relation that is a non-relation.
Whether or not you can divorce the fundamental notion of being born into the symbolic order from a reading of Lacan and objects is a great question; and one that I don't have a definite answer to.
As to why OOO exists...well, if you've read Graham Harman, Levi Bryant, Timothy Morton, and Ian Bogost and still don't see a reason/purpose, I'm not sure how much help I can be. OOO, for me, is perhaps more than anything a broad posthumanist way of thinking about the world. Instead of tranhumanism (or cyborg posthumanism) and animal studies, OOO works from a flat ontological plane -- placing all things, humans and nonhumans, on the same ontological status. As Bogost has said, this does not mean that all things exist equally but that all things equally exist. A copper coin is just as real (and just as much of an object in the world) as a Dachshund. If the goal of posthumanism is to blur the boundary between culture and nature, human and nonhuman, subject and object, then OOO is about as extreme as you can get.
I hope this helps,
Nathan